"There is a set of Fs" implies only logical truths
Nominalists and anti-nominalists disagree about whether there are, for example, sets of things, where the things in question may be "concrete". The sentence "there is a set of chairs" is an example of a mixed mathematical claim. It uses the (presumably) non-mathematical predicate "x is a chair" as the defining formula in an instance of the Comprehension Scheme:
with yields:
contains non-mathematical vocabulary. Suppose that we call sentences containing only "concrete" predicates nom-sentences; call instances of the Comprehension Scheme using only nom-formulas comp-axioms. The simplest relevant conservativeness result says:
Here is the simplest proof of the simplest kind of conservativeness result which will give a flavour of why comprehension axioms are conservative. We consider the simplest scenario: the nom-language is a first-order language (with identity) and has only a single unary concrete predicate and we consider the simplest comp-axiom, , where we write to mean "x is an element of y". The conservativeness result now is: for any -sentence ,
from to a derivation of entirely in logic. I will assume a Hilbert-style deductive system with linear derivations, some bunch of axiom schemes and the single rule Modus Ponens.
First, note that, in general, if , then (where is a new constant: it is skolem constant). So, it will be sufficient to show that we can do this given a derivation of from . Let be the result of extending with the new constant . The main idea of the proof is that the assumption looks just like a "definition" of . So, the plan is to consider each formula in the derivation, and replace any occurrence of in by (where are terms). This replacement therefore eliminates the symbol (i.e., the membership predicate). Let be the result of making this replacement.
From the definition of "derivation", each is either an axiom of logic, or is the assumption formula , or is obtained by Modus Ponens on previous formulas. The hope is that, after the replacements, the new sequence of formulas is, "more or less", a derivation of B in logic.
Since does not contain the symbol , the replacement makes no difference to . (I.e., is just .) Next, if is a logical axiom containing , then replacing by will give a logical axiom in . Next, if is the assumption formula , then replacing by yields . But this is itself a logically derivable -sentence. Finally, if is obtained by Modus Ponens from and (with ), we need to check that after we've made the replacements, then result is still an instance of Modus Ponens. The only thing to check is that applying the replacement to a conditional yields the conditional of applying the replacements; and this is so. (I.e., that is .) It follows then that, assuming we "paste in" the missing derivation of , the replacement yields a derivation of in logic alone, in the language . However, since does not contain , if there is a logical derivation of in , then there is a logical derivation of in itself. So, , as required.
This is probably the simplest case of a Field-style conservativeness result for mathematical axioms over "nominalistic" sentences. One can then build-up to more complicated cases by modifying this kind of proof. E.g., to consider comp-axioms where the defining formula is , where is any -formula (rather just the atomic formula ). Also, to consider a nom-language with various primitive predicates for concreta. In these latter cases, the comp-axioms have the form , where is an -formula and is a constant (a new constant is needed for each formula ). The method is, again, to replace occurrences of the atomic formula as they appear in a derivation by certain -formulas. This will transform a given derivation using comp-axioms into a derivation in logic alone (in the language ).
- If there is a derivation of a nom-sentence
from a comp-axiom, there is also a derivation of from logic.
Here is the simplest proof of the simplest kind of conservativeness result which will give a flavour of why comprehension axioms are conservative. We consider the simplest scenario: the nom-language
.
First, note that, in general, if
From the definition of "derivation", each
Since
This is probably the simplest case of a Field-style conservativeness result for mathematical axioms over "nominalistic" sentences. One can then build-up to more complicated cases by modifying this kind of proof. E.g., to consider comp-axioms where the defining formula is
Comments
Post a Comment