The best medieval solution to the Liar ever
It's been much too long since I last posted here at M-Phi! (I've been unusually busy with all kinds of things.) What follows here is still not a proper post: it is in fact a review of Stephen Read's edition and translation of Bradwardine's treatise on insolubles, which I just wrote for Speculum. But I figured that it may be of general interest -- after all, any M-Phi'er worthy of the title should be familiar with Bradwardine on the Liar.
--------------------------------------------------
--------------------------------------------------
Thomas Bradwardine (first half of the 14th
century) is well known for his decisive contributions to physics (he was one of
the founders of the Merton School of Calculators) as well as for his
theological work, in particular his defense of Augustinianism in De Causa Dei. He also led an eventful
life, accompanying Edward III to the battlefield as his confessor, and dying of
the Black Death in 1349 one week after a hasty return to England to take up his
new appointment as the Archbishop of Canterbury.
What is thus far less well known about
Bradwardine is that, prior to these adventures, in the early to mid-1320s, he
worked extensively on logical topics. In this period, he composed his logical tour de force: his treatise on
insolubles. Insolubles were logical puzzles to which Latin medieval authors
devoted a considerable amount of attention (Spade & Read 2009). What is
special about insolubles is that they often involve some kind of self-reference
or self-reflection. The paradigmatic insoluble is what is now known (not a term
used by the medieval authors themselves) as the liar paradox: ‘This sentence is not true’. If it is true, then it
is not true; but if it is not true, then what it says about itself is correct,
namely that it is not true, and thus it is true after all. Hence, we are forced
to conclude that the sentence is both true and false, which violates the principle
of bivalence. It is interesting to note that, in the hands of Tarski, Kripke
and other towering figures, the liar and similar paradoxes re-emerged in the 20th
century as one of the main topics within philosophy of logic and philosophical
logic, and remain to this day a much discussed topic.
Bradwardine’s De insolubilibus has been recently given its first critical
edition, accompanied by an English translation and an extensive introduction,
by Stephen Read. One cannot overestimate the importance of the publication of
this volume for the study of the history of logic as a whole; prior to this
edition, Bradwardine’s text was available in print only in an unreliable edition
by M.L. Roure in 1970. Moreover, Bradwardine’s treatise is arguably the most
important medieval treatise on the topic. So far, the general philosophical
audience is mostly familiar with John Buridan's approach to insolubles;
the relevant passages from chapter 8 of his Sophismata
have received multiple English translations and been extensively discussed. But
Buridan's text pales in comparison to Bradwardine’s treatise; Bradwardine not only
offers a detailed account and refutation of previously held positions (chapters
2 to 5), but he also presents his own novel, revolutionary solution (chapters 6
to 12).
The backbone of Bradwardine’s solution is
the idea that sentences typically signify several things, not only their most
apparent signification. In particular, they signify everything they entail.
Moreover, Bradwardine postulates that, for a sentence to be true, everything it signifies must be the
case; in other words, he associates the notion of truth to universal quantification over what a sentence says. Accordingly, a
sentence is false if at least one of the things it signifies is not the case (existential quantification). He then goes on to prove that insoluble sentences
say of themselves not only that they are not true, but also that they are true.
Hence, such sentences say two contradictory things, which can never both
obtain; so at least one of them is not the case, and thus such sentences are simply
false.
Unlike Buridan, who merely postulates
without further argumentation that every sentence implies that it is true,
Bradwardine makes no such assumption, and instead proves (through a rather
subtle argument, reconstructed in section 5 of Read’s introduction) that
specific sentences, namely insolubles, say of themselves that they are true. In
this sense, Bradwardine’s analysis can rightly be said to be more sophisticated
and compelling than Buridan’s.
Bradwardine’s solution to insolubles is not
only of interest to the historian of logic, and indeed Read and others have
written extensively on its significance for contemporary debates on paradoxes
of self-reference. In fact, a whole volume was published on the philosophical
significance of Bradwardine’s analysis (Rahman et al. 2008). According to Read,
the Bradwardinian framework allows for the treatment of a wide range of
paradoxes as well as for the development of a conceptually motivated,
paradox-resistant theory of truth in terms of quantification over what a
sentence says. Alas, the latter project was not to succeed, for the following
reason. As pointed out by Read himself in his critique of Buridan (Read 2002),
a theory that says that every sentence signifies (implies) its own truth cannot
offer an effective definition of truth, as every sentence becomes what is known
as a truth-teller: one necessary condition for its truth is that be true (as it
is one of the things it says), ensuing a fatal form of circularity. Now, as it
turns out, while Bradwardine does not postulate that every sentence signifies
its own truth, this does follow as a corollary from his general principles
(Dutilh Novaes 2011). Thus, Read’s own criticism against Buridan’s approach
applies to Bradwardine as well. This does not affect the Bradwardine/Read
solutions to the paradoxes because all of them (paradoxes) come out as false, but ultimately
Bradwardine cannot deliver a satisfactory theory of truth.
However, this observation should in no way
be construed as a criticism of Read’s work in general and of his edition and
translation of Bradwardine’s treatise in particular. It is indeed the job of a
reviewer to spot shortcomings in a volume, even if only minor ones, but this
reviewer failed miserably at this endeavor. Read’s volume is an absolutely
exemplary combination of historical and textual rigor (for the edition and translation
of the text) with philosophical insight into the conceptual intricacies of the
material; it is both accessible and sophisticated. As such, it is to be
emphatically recommended to anyone interested in the history of logic as well
as in modern discussions on paradoxes and self-reference.
Interesting! Can you tell us a few of your favorite examples of the 'insolubles' Bradwardine studied, other than the Liar? And by the way, what did he call the Liar?
ReplyDeleteHi John, I left the book in my office, so a proper reply will have to wait until tomorrow, ok? But the Liar was just one insoluble among others for the medievals, albeit the one most extensively discussed by them; it did not have a special name. In fact, I wonder when the Liar was first referred to as the 'Liar'. I think Russell used the exact term, and there is also a German book called Der Lugner. Theorie, Geschichte und Auflosung (by A. Rustow, 1910). Coming to think of it, it was probably Russell, but I'd have to look it up.
Delete¨
Hi again. So some of the other examples discussed by Bradwardine are what we now refer to as epistemic paradoxes, such as 'This sentence is not known by you' (very much like the knower paradox). He discusses those in chap. 9 of the treatise.
DeleteI'll have to go read Dutilh Novaes 2011: it's not obvious to me what exactly the problem about being a truth-teller is. For your account of Read, I'd need to know what the conditions on giving a definition of truth are. For your account of your objection, I'd need to know how "a fatal form of circularity" is generated. It looks like being a truth-teller is "light" and so might not burden any story with enough substance to generate problems; might be light enough that it's just automatically satisfied if everything else is.
ReplyDeleteUnfortunately, the review is supposed to be around 900 words (it's already longer than that), so I can't really spell out the details in it. My goal has been to entice people's curiosity so that they go look for themselves :) (Seems to have worked with you...)
DeleteThe argument is on pp 68-71 of my 2011 article. The main point is the following:
"But it [the proposed definition of truth] can never show in a definitive way that a sentence is true, since one of the necessary conditions for the truth of a sentence is precisely that it is true: the definition corresponds to a looping, non-terminating procedure." In other words, you end up with the same thing on the definiens AND the definiendum side of the definition (to be sure, more stuff in the definiens side).
Hi Catarina,
ReplyDeleteThanks for adding a bit of activity to M-Phi's recent, hopefully temporary, dormancy! (I'm so busy with the new job.)
Something I'm not sure about - are Bradwardine's truth bearers sentences or propositions?
Jeff
Hi Jeff! I can imagine how busy you must be at your new job, constantly changing from togas to gowns and having copious dinners at colleges.
DeleteBut anyway, the issue of what truth bearers are for Bradwardine and other medieval authors is complicated. It's certainly not propositions (in the modern sense), but there is still the debate between types and tokens. Stephen and I don't entirely agree on this one; I think Bradwardine individuates sentential meaning in terms of tokens, while Stephen thinks it is in terms of types. My main argument is that the very core of Bradwardine's shield against revenge presupposes tokens: Socrates' assertion 'Socrates says something false' (and nothing else) says of itself that it is true (as per the argument referred to but not explained above), whereas my assertion 'Socrates says something false' does no such thing, and thus it is not an insoluble (paradoxical). I discuss these matters in my 2009 PQ paper, 'Lessons on sentential meaning...'
No togas; but some amusing dinners, yes.
ReplyDeleteSo not propositions in the modern sense, but either sentence types or sentence tokens? In your example, the types (i.e., the string "S"^"o"^"c"...^"l"^"s"^"e") of the two speech acts are identical (because linguistic strings are individuated by syntax alone) whereas the context has changed. That truth for sentence types is context dependent is the standard view: the semantic primitive is "string S expresses (in L) in context C the proposition A".
In this case, if we call the sentence S, then since the context is different, S is self-referential in the first context, but S is not self-referential in the second. I guess that "S expresses (In L) in context C the proposition A" is something like "S signifies the proposition A".
So, whether this is a viable approach to the liar paradox will turn on the properties of this semantic primitive of "signifying" or "expressing". It seems likely to me that a revenge issue may arise because, possibly, one can show that no sufficiently rich interpreted language L can contain its own "signifies" predicate.
Jeff
This is a complicated bit of the theory (just as the bit about types/tokens): what are the 'things' that a sentence signifies? At some point Stephen seemed to suggest that these should be sentences too, but I argued against that in my 2009 PQ paper. it has to be something else, perhaps close to the modern notion of propositions.
DeleteHere's a possible revenge sentence: "This sentence signifies other than is the case'. If it signifies as is the case, then it doesn't; if it does not, then it does. So while the truth predicate seems to be brought under control by means of the quantificational definition, now all the paradoxical burden can be transfered to the notion of signifying.
Hi Catarina,
ReplyDeleteWhat I'm guessing is that the theory has the following axioms
(1) $T(x) \leftrightarrow \Pi p(Sig(x, \langle p \rangle) \rightarrow p)$.
(2) $Sig(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner, \langle \phi \rangle)$.
(3) $\Sigma p(p \leftrightarrow \phi)$.
where $\Pi$ and $\Sigma$ are substitutional/second-order quantifiers (for sentence variables), $Sig(x,y)$ is the primitive "signifies" predicate, and (3) is comprehension for sentence variables.
Then I think we can prove:
(T-Out) $T(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner) \rightarrow \phi)$.
But we can't prove (T-In). To prove that we should need,
(4) $Sig(x, \langle \phi \rangle) \wedge Sig(x, \langle \theta \rangle) \rightarrow (\phi \leftrightarrow \theta)$.
But (4) requires that all things a sentence signifies be materially equivalent, which is not so for the sentence which says of itself it is not true.
So, the theory avoids inconsistency by avoiding (4).
Does that sound right?
Jeff
Yes, that's exactly right, the theory does not have T-In as an axiom: from Phi you don't get T('Phi'). I discuss this in more detail in my paper in the Rahman et al. volume, called 'Tarski's hidden theory of meaning'.
Delete