Two objections to Priest's Inclosure Schema
(My student Rein van der Laan will be defending his
Bachelors thesis on Priest’s Inclosure Schema this week. It was in the
process of supervising him that I developed my current ideas on the topic, which means
that the content of this post is basically joint work with Rein.)
In a number of papers (such as this 1994 paper) and in his book Beyond the Limits of Thought (BtLoT), Graham Priest defends the
claim that all paradoxes of self-reference can be adequately captured by the
Inclosure Schema IS, which he formulates in the following way:
(1) Ω = {y; φ(y)} exists and ψ(Ω) Existence
(2) if x ⊆ Ω and ψ(x) (a) δ(x) ∉ x Transcendence
(b)
δ(x) ∈ Ω Closure
The different paradoxes of self-reference would be generated
by different instantiations of the schematic letters of the schema (for details,
consult BtLoT).
There have been quite some articles discussing IS in the
meantime (among others: Abad, Grattan-Guinness, Badici, and responses by Priest and Weber), where a
number of interesting objections have been raised against the idea that IS
successfully describes all paradoxes of self-reference (the Liar, Russell’s
paradox etc). Here I discuss two (not necessarily novel) objections that I think are quite
problematic for Priest’s general project with IS -- in particular, that of
arguing for the Principle of Uniform
Solution: similar paradoxes must receive similar solutions.
(Unsurprisingly, he goes on to claim that only dialethism is able to offer an
uniform solution to all these paradoxes.)
The
over/undergeneration objection. One plausible way to understand what Priest
is up to with IS is that it is intended as a formal explanans for the informal
notion of ‘paradoxes of self-reference’. If this is correct, then it is
legitimate to raise the question of whether IS gets the extension of the
informal concept right; it may overgenerate (arguments which we do not want to
count as self-referential paradoxes would fit into the schema) and/or
undergenerate (it may fail to capture arguments which we do want to count as
self-referential paradoxes).
As it turns out, IS seems both to over- and undergenerate.
It overgenerates in that a number of reductio
arguments which are not paradoxical, properly speaking, seem to conform to IS
(as pointed out e.g. by Abad). One example would be Cantor’s diagonal argument
for the uncountability of the real numbers (see this earlier blog post of mine for a presentation of the argument). And it undergenerates in that Curry’s
paradox, which obviously (?) should count as a self-referential paradox, cannot be
accounted for by means of IS. Priest is well aware of this limitation, but
retorts:
[Curry] paradoxes belong to a quite different family. [They] do not involve negation and, a fortiori, contradiction. They therefore have nothing to do with contradictions at the limits of thought. (BtLoT, 169)
This seems odd, as the original claim seemed to be that IS
was meant to describe paradoxes of self-reference in general, not only those
involving a negation. (To be fair, Curry is the hardest of all paradoxes; as
Graham himself says, Curry is hard on everyone…) At any rate, if IS both over- and
undergenerates as a formal explanans of paradoxes of self-reference (which is at least what the original 1994 paper seems to claim it should be), this is
not good news for Priest’s general project. (He may, of course, say that Curry falls out of the scope of IS and thus of the Principle of Uniform Solution, but the overgeneration charge still stands.)
The form/matter
objection. A useful and frequently cited definition of paradoxes is the one
offered by Sainsbury (2009, 1): what characterizes a paradox is “an apparently unacceptable
conclusion derived by apparently acceptable reasoning from apparently
acceptable premises.” This means that one crucial component of a paradox is
the degree of belief an agent
attributes to the premises and the cogency of the reasoning, and the degree of disbelief she attributes to
the conclusion. The ‘apparently’ clause does not need to entail a relativistic
conception of paradoxes, but it does mean that a paradox has a perspectival component. Galileo’s
paradox was paradoxical for Galileo and many others, but not for Cantor, who
did not see the conclusion of the reasoning as unacceptable.
Now, there
is an old but by now largely forgotten conception of the form and matter of an
argument according to which the matter of the argument is the ‘quality’ of its
premises. In this vein, a materially defective argument is one where the
premises are false, while a formally defective argument is one where the
reasoning is not valid. (See this article of mine for the historical background of
this conception.) On the basis of this idea, we could say that
the matter of an argument corresponds to one’s degree of belief/disbelief in
the premises/conclusion (again, perspectival), and the form corresponds to the
structure of the argument. This would entail that paradoxes come in degrees, in
function of the agent's degrees of (dis)belief in the premises, reasoning and
conclusion.
With this
distinction in mind, we can see why IS fails to capture the extension of the
concept of paradoxes of self-reference: it captures only the form of such arguments, but is silent
concerning their matter (understood as the degrees of (dis)belief in premises and conclusion). The
paradoxical nature of a paradox, however, is crucially determined by the degrees
of (dis)belief in the premises and conclusion (as made clear in Sainsbury’s
quote). [UPDATE: this sentence has been misunderstood by many people. Notice that I am here using an unconventional understanding of the matter of an argument (introduced in the previous paragraph), not the more familiar schematic notion of form vs. matter.] This is why IS cannot differentiate between a
truly paradoxical argument and a reductio
argument, intended to establish the falsity of one of the premises rather than being truly paradoxical.
[UPDATE: In BtLoT Priest introduces the restriction that different instantiations of IS must yield true premises for an argument to count as an instantiation of IS, and thus to be an inclosure paradox. This is why the Barber then does not count as an inclosure paradox. This restriction seems to me to be too strong, as often what is under discussion when a paradox emerges is whether the apparently acceptable premises are indeed as acceptable as they seem.]
[UPDATE: In BtLoT Priest introduces the restriction that different instantiations of IS must yield true premises for an argument to count as an instantiation of IS, and thus to be an inclosure paradox. This is why the Barber then does not count as an inclosure paradox. This restriction seems to me to be too strong, as often what is under discussion when a paradox emerges is whether the apparently acceptable premises are indeed as acceptable as they seem.]
So
ultimately, the conclusion seems to be that IS fails to deliver what Priest
wants it to deliver. Nevertheless, I firmly believe that the formulation of IS
has been one of the most interesting and important developments in research on
paradoxes of the last decades. It forces us to think about paradoxes with a much-needed
higher level of generality, and thus leads to a new, deeper understanding of
the phenomenon – even if the conclusion must be that IS cannot be the whole story
after all.
UPDATE: Some further thoughts on the Inclosure Schema here.
UPDATE: Some further thoughts on the Inclosure Schema here.
I am very surprised by the statement "[Curry] paradoxes belong to a quite different family. [They] do not involve negation and, a fortiori, contradiction.", see also https://plus.google.com/u/0/116887476001511997780/posts/NBvhWqHa4cq
ReplyDeleteIn a forthcoming (co-authored) paper, Priest explains in more detail why he claims that Curry is a different beast altogether. In particular, because it does not need to involve a consequent that is false or impossible, there are versions of Curry which do not involve negation in the way you point out. So take C: If C is true, it is sunny today. By the usual means, one can prove that it is sunny today, which happens to be true (where I am at least), but it is still highly suspicious that this gets established in this way.
DeleteSo now Priest et al say that Curry is not an Inclosure paradox, or a paradox of contradiction. That's fine, but then the original explanandum, which was supposed to be the concept of paradoxes of self-reference, has now become something else.
This comment has been removed by the author.
DeleteIn my opinion a form (X -> Y) is a generalization of negation. The left hand side of an implication in a positive context forms a negative context, etc.. This is known as sub formula polarity. So I consider Curry a generalized paradoxon of contradiction.
DeleteThe curry paradoxon symbolizes one trajectory of attack when for example dealing with paradoxes of comprehension. The comprehension schema exists y forall x (x in y <-> A(x)) has its limits. For example using A(x) = ~(x in x), one finds y_0 in y_0 <-> ~(y_0 in y_0).
The set theory attack is to bound the witness, so that the modified comprehension schema would read exists y forall x(x in y <-> A(x) & x in z). The attack symbolized by the Curry paradoxon is to find a logic that doesn't collapse for y_0 in y_0 <-> ~(y_0 in y_0).
The most simple proof of Currys paradoxon in LM (= positive propositional logic) shows that paraconsistent logics such as LM don't help. LM does not have ex falso quodlibet, but nevertheless admits Curry paradoxon. That's how I arrived at the paradoxon.
I stopped then, and started using type theory to bound the comprehension. But I guess it is also possible to tweak the logic, for example by removing contraction. This would not allow the last step in my G+ proof, since there the premisse x -> x -> y is comming from two branches. Right?
So why ban the Curry paradox? Its a real jewel.
This comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteThis comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteThis comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDelete