Buchak on risk and rationality
I'm very honoured to be part of the Author Meets Critics session on Lara Buchak's new book Risk and Rationality
at the Pacific APA in San Diego this April (Buchak 2014). It is a brilliantly
insightful and closely argued book that I feel sure will be at the
centre of a number of debates in decision theory over the next few
years. At the heart of the book is an alternative to expected utility
theory that is intended to incorporate an agent's attitude to risk as a
component of rational practical decision making along with the utilities
and credences on which orthodox expected utility theory is based. I'd
like to write a series of posts about this alternative to orthodox
expected utility theory that Buchak proposes. So I'll start in this
post with an overview of that alternative. Needless to say, this is no
substitute for reading the book, which is absolutely full of rich
explanation and philosophical insights that demand a lot of reflection.
Let us begin with the framework in which Buchak formulates both expected utility theory and her own alternative to it. There are three main ingredients to the background framework:
of acts.
The internal attitudes are typically taken to be given by the agent's
credences in propositions in a -algebra on
and her utilities for outcomes in : however,
one of Buchak's central contentions is that there is a third type of
internal attitude with which decision theory deals, namely, attitudes to
risk. If one is a constructivist about the internal attitudes, then
one will take only the external attitudes to be real: one will then
take the business of decision theory to be the representation of the
external attitudes by treating the agent as if she has internal
attitudes and as if she combines those attitudes in a particular
way to give her external attitudes. If one is a realist about the
internal attitudes, then one will take both sorts of attitudes to be
real: one will then say that a rational agent's internal and external
attitudes ought to relate in a particular way; indeed, they ought to
relate as if she obtains her external attitudes by combining her
internal attitudes in a particular way.
Expected utility theory posits only two types of internal attitudes: these are given by the agent's credences and utilities. Her credences measure how strongly she believes the propositions in : they are given by a
probability function . Her utilities measure
how strongly she desires or values the outcomes in the set
: they are given by a utility function . As with most decision theories, expected
utility theory posits one type of external attitude: this is given by
the agent's preference ordering, which is a binary relation
on the set of acts ; says that the agent weakly prefers to .
Expected utility theory then employs the following rule of
combination, which states how her internal and external attitudes ought
to relate:
The EU rule of combination Suppose . Then let
Then it ought to be that
That is, an agent's preferences ought to order acts by their subjective expected utility.
Thus, for instance, consider the act , where
and
Then the following figure illustrates the expected utility of .
It is
obtained by taking a weighted sum of the utilities of the possible
outcomes, where the weight given to a particular outcome is given by the
probability that the outcome will result from .
Fig. 1 suggests two ways in which we might reformulate . These will be very useful in understanding how expected
utility theory relates to Buchak's proposal.
First reformulation First, it is clear that depends only on the utilities of
the outcomes to which the act may give rise and the probabilities
that will produce outcomes with those utilities. Thus, given an act
and a utility function , we
might redescribe as where
relative to .
Then
Then Fig. 2 illustrates this reformulation of expected utility for our example act .
Second reformulation The second reformulation of builds on this first and is
illustrated in Fig. 3. Suppose is the ordered utility-based description of
relative to . Then
Again, the expected utility of an act is given by a weighted sum: but this time the quantities to be weighted are the differences between one possible utility and the possible utility immediately below it; and the weight assigned to that difference is the probability that the act will give rise to at least that much utility.
Tails}, £50} and Risky = {Heads, £100; Tails, £0}. Suppose that our agent strictly prefers Safe
to Risky: that is, Safe Risky. Can
expected utility theory capture the rationality of this preference?
Suppose that, since the coin is known to be fair, rationality requires
that the agent assign (Heads) = 0.5 = (Tails). Then it is still possible to describe a
utility function on the outcomes £0, £50, £100 that generates these preferences in the way expected utility theory
requires. Let and . That is, suppose the
agent treats money as a dependent good: how much utility it
gives depends on how much of it she has already; so, money has
diminishing marginal utility for this agent. Then, for an agent with
this credence function and utility function, (Safe)
> (Risky), as required. So expected utility theory can
capture the rationality of these preferences. However, as Buchak
rightly observes, those preferences seem rational not only for an agent
for whom money has diminishing marginal utility; they seem rational even
for an agent whose utility is linear in money. And this is something
that expected utility cannot capture. Thus, Buchak is interested not
only in saving the Allais preferences, but also in saving other
risk-sensitive behaviour without attributing the risk-sensitive
behaviour to the shape of the utility function.
How does Buchak hope to capture these risk-sensitive preferences? Where expected utility theory countenances only two types of internal attitude as relevant to preferences, Buchak countenances a third as well: this third component is supposed to capture the agent's attitude to risk, and it is given by a function , which Buchak assumes to be strictly
increasing, continuous, and taking the following values, and
. (As Buchak explains, her proposal
is closely related to proposals by (Quiggin 1982), (Machina & Schmeidler, 1992), and (Köbberling & Wakker, 2003)).
Buchak's risk-weighted expected utility theory then employs the following rule of combination, which states how an agent's internal and external attitudes ought to relate, where the agent has credence function , utility function , and risk function :
The REU rule of combination Suppose is the ordered utility-based description
of relative to . Then let
Then it ought to be that
In Fig. 4, we illustrate the risk-weighted expected utility of our example act when the agent has the risk function
.
Notice that the formulation of is
exactly like the formulation of that we gave above except
that each probability weight is transformed by the agent's risk
function. Thus, if (for all ), then, as
Fig. 4 illustrates, the lowest utility to which the act
can give rise--namely, --contributes just as much to as it does to --it contributes to both. But
further increases in utility--such as the increase from minimum
utility of to minimum utility of --make less of a
contribution since their probability-- --is acted on
by the risk function, and it is this reduced value-- --that weights the possible increases in utility. Thus, such an
agent displays risk-averse behaviour. is such a risk function.
Similarly, if (for all ), then the lowest utility
to which the act can give rise contributes just as much to as it does to , but further increases in utility
make more of a contribution since their probability is acted on by the
risk function and it is this increased value that weights the possible
increases in utility. This is illustrated in Fig. 5.
Such an agent displays risk-seeking behaviour. is such a risk function.
It's also easy to see that, if (for ), then
. Thus, expected utility theory is
the special case of risk-weighted expected utility theory given by a
linear risk function. In such a situation, we say that the agent is risk-neutral. This means that Buchak's theory permits any
preferences that expected utility theory permits. But it also permits a
whole lot more. For instance, one can easily recover the Allais
preferences or the preference Safe Risky
described above by attributing to an agent a certain sort of risk
function--in both cases, a risk-averse risk function.
This, then, is Buchak's proposal. In the book, she presents a representation theorem for the REU rule of combination. That is, she presents axioms for a preference ordering such that satisfies those axioms iff there is a unique probability function , a unique risk function , and a unique-up-to-affine-transformation utility function such that
She also defends her proposal as the only way to understand risk-sensitive agents that still interprets them as engaged in means-end or instrumental reasoning. I hope to write more about the latter topic in the next post.
Expected utility
Let us begin with the framework in which Buchak formulates both expected utility theory and her own alternative to it. There are three main ingredients to the background framework:
is the set of states (or possible worlds). Degrees of belief or credences will be assigned to a -algebra of subsets of : these are propositions represented as sets of states or possible worlds. is the set of outcomes. Utilities will be assigned to the elements of . is the set of acts. These are finite-valued functions from to . Thus, we can represent an act as , where are the values of and is the proposition that will have outcome (we assume that this proposition is in )---that is, . For each outcome , there is an act such that for all states . We call this the constant act on . Let be the set of constant acts.
- The set of states may be taken to be
= {Heads, Tails}; - The set of outcomes may be taken to be
; - The two options between which our agent is choosing belong to the set
of acts. They are Safe = {Heads Tails}, £50} and Risky = {Heads, £100; Tails, £0}. Note that Safe = [£50]; that is, Safe is the constant act on £50.
Expected utility theory posits only two types of internal attitudes: these are given by the agent's credences and utilities. Her credences measure how strongly she believes the propositions in
The EU rule of combination Suppose
Then it ought to be that
That is, an agent's preferences ought to order acts by their subjective expected utility.
Thus, for instance, consider the act
and
Then the following figure illustrates the expected utility of
![]() |
Fig. 1: |
Fig. 1 suggests two ways in which we might reformulate
First reformulation First, it is clear that
are the utilities to which might give rise ordered from least to greatest---that is, . For instance, in our example act : , , . is the proposition that will give rise to . For instance, in our example act : , , .
Then
Then Fig. 2 illustrates this reformulation of expected utility for our example act
![]() |
Fig. 2: |
Second reformulation The second reformulation of
Again, the expected utility of an act is given by a weighted sum: but this time the quantities to be weighted are the differences between one possible utility and the possible utility immediately below it; and the weight assigned to that difference is the probability that the act will give rise to at least that much utility.
![]() |
Risk-weighted expected utility
With this in hand, we're ready to formulate Buchak's alternative to expected utility theory. Buchak is motivated by the apparent rationality of risk-sensitive behaviour. Notoriously, some seemingly rational risk-sensitive behaviour cannot be captured by expected utility theory at all: for instance, Allais described seemingly rational preferences that cannot be generated by any rational credence function and utility function in the way prescribed by expected utility theory (Allais 1953). Moreover, there are other seemingly rationally preferences that can be generated by a credence function and utility function in line with expected utility theory, but which seem to be rational even for agents who do not have credences and utilities that would generate them in this way. Thus, for instance, consider the two acts described at the beginning of this section: Safe = {HeadsHow does Buchak hope to capture these risk-sensitive preferences? Where expected utility theory countenances only two types of internal attitude as relevant to preferences, Buchak countenances a third as well: this third component is supposed to capture the agent's attitude to risk, and it is given by a function
Buchak's risk-weighted expected utility theory then employs the following rule of combination, which states how an agent's internal and external attitudes ought to relate, where the agent has credence function
The REU rule of combination Suppose
Then it ought to be that
In Fig. 4, we illustrate the risk-weighted expected utility of our example act
![]() |
Fig. 4: |
Notice that the formulation of
Similarly, if
![]() |
It's also easy to see that, if
This, then, is Buchak's proposal. In the book, she presents a representation theorem for the REU rule of combination. That is, she presents axioms for a preference ordering such that
She also defends her proposal as the only way to understand risk-sensitive agents that still interprets them as engaged in means-end or instrumental reasoning. I hope to write more about the latter topic in the next post.
References
- Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: critique des postulats et axiomes de l’école Américaine. Econometrica, 21(4):503-546.
- Buchak, L. (2014). Risk and Rationality. Oxford University Press.
- Köbberling, V. & P. Wakker (2003). Preference Foundations for Nonexpected Utility Theory: A Generalized and Simplified Technique. Mathematics of Operations Research, 28(3):39-423
- Machina, M. J. & D. Schmeidler (1992) A More Robust Definition of Subjective Probability. Econometrica, 60(4):745-80.
- Quiggin, J. (1982) A Theory of Anticipated Utility. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3:323-43.
I think Buchak has done a great job here. I am a little sketchy on my formal logic, however the concept is in my view sound. For me it opens up all sorts of existential notions about how I live my life and the choices I make.
ReplyDelete