Review of T. Parsons' Articulating Medieval Logic
By Catarina Dutilh Novaes
(Cross-posted at NewAPPS)
I was asked to write a review of Terry Parsons' Articulating Medieval Logic for the Australasian Journal of Philosophy. This is what I've come up with so far. Comments welcome!
=======================
(Cross-posted at NewAPPS)
I was asked to write a review of Terry Parsons' Articulating Medieval Logic for the Australasian Journal of Philosophy. This is what I've come up with so far. Comments welcome!
=======================
Scholars working on (Latin) medieval logic can be viewed as populating a spectrum. At one extremity are those who adopt a purely historical
and textual approach to the material: they are the ones who produce the
invaluable modern editions of important texts, without which the field would to
a great extent simply not exist; they also typically seek to place the
doctrines presented in the texts in a broader historical context. At the other
extremity are those who study the medieval theories first and foremost from the
point of view of modern philosophical and logical concerns; various techniques
of formalization are then employed to ‘translate’ the medieval theories into
something more intelligible to the modern non-historian philosopher. Between
the two extremes one encounters a variety of positions. (Notice that one and
the same scholar can at times wear the historian’s hat, and at other times
the systematic philosopher’s hat.) For those adopting one of the many
intermediary positions, life can be hard at times: when trying to combine
the two paradigms, these scholars sometimes end up displeasing everyone (speaking
from personal experience).
Terence Parsons’ Articulating
Medieval Logic occupies one of these intermediate positions, but very close to the second extremity; indeed, it represents
the daring attempt to combine the author’s expertise in natural language
semantics, linguistics, and modern philosophy with his interest in medieval
logical theories (which arose in particular from his decade-long collaboration
with Calvin Normore, to whom the book is dedicated). For scholars of Latin medieval
logic, the fact that such a distinguished expert in contemporary philosophy and
linguistics became interested in these medieval theories only confirms what
we’ve known all along: medieval logical theories have intrinsic systematic
interest; they are not only curious museum pieces.
Despite not being the first to employ modern logical
techniques to analyze medieval theories, Parsons' approach is quite unique (one
might even say idiosyncratic). It seems fair to say that nobody has ever before attempted to achieve what he wants to achieve with this book. A passage from
the book’s Introduction is quite revealing with respect to its goals:
It has been suggested that I am
trying to impersonate a 15th-century logician who happens to have
the skills and habits of a 21st-century graduate student. I discuss
known medieval views with some care, and show how far one can go without
introducing any logical principles beyond the medieval ones. (p. 4)
Prima facie, this seems like an accurate description of
the whole project. However, the first sentence is not quite true, and in fact there is something of a tension between the two sentences in this
passage. The main goal of the book is indeed to ‘show how far one can go’ with
only medieval logical principles; the conclusion of the book is that one can go very
far, in fact pretty much as far as modern logical theories, as argued in chap.
9 (medieval logic also encompasses fragments of modal logic, a topic treated in
chap. 10). But what does it mean to ‘go far’ here? What Parsons seems to mean
is something quite modern, and indeed rather un-medieval: what is the deductive
power of the system? What is its expressive power? How many non-trivial
theorems can one prove with just a few basic principles?
Now, the idea of designing logical systems containing just a
few basic rules and principles and yet being able to prove a lot with it – which
could be described as a principle of logical economy – is simply not a significant
concern for medieval logicians. True enough, insofar as they inherited the
ideals of the Aristotelian axiomatic model of science, in particular the
desideratum of parsimony with respect to the establishment of first principles,
this principle of economy is not entirely alien to medieval logicians. However,
it can be plausibly argued that, in practice, this was simply not something
medieval logicians cared much about (Parsons of course knows this: ‘there were
only a few attempts to carry out the project of deriving most principles from a
basic few’ (p. 1)). Medieval treatises often contain extensive lists of basic
principles and definitions, and while the authors were familiar with the idea
of deriving conclusions and new principles from the more primitive ones (see
e.g. Burley’s On the Purity of the Art of Logic, or as noted by Parsons, Buridan’s Treatise on Consequences), the idea of seeing ‘how far one can go’ with just a few
principles – which is a distinctively meta-theoretical question – is not a goal that most medieval
logicians would have readily recognized as worth pursuing.
And so, it seems somewhat inaccurate to describe the book’s project
as that of impersonating ‘a 15th-century logician who happens to
have the skills and habits of a 21st-century graduate student’; what
we encounter is not only 21st-century skills and habits, but also 21st-century
goals. What remains purely medieval
are the basic principles and rules of the system, and the project of
investigating the deductive and expressive power of this collection of
principles and rules is philosophically a very interesting one. Indeed, as
Parsons notes on p. 259, his results put pressure on the Fregean claim that a
thoroughly artificial language is required for scientific purposes, given the
hopeless inadequacy of the ‘languages of life’. Parsons’ results show that the
Fregean indispensability claim is not nearly as obviously true as is usually
thought, given that medieval logic is by and large based on regimented versions of medieval Latin.
But what are these
famous basic principles? Parsons isolates three principles as fundamental: (in modern
terms) indirect derivation (or reductio), existential instantiation, and
existential generalization. The last two correspond to the technique of ekthesis, already known to Aristotle and
passed on to the medievals in various forms (e.g. the notion of expository
syllogism). (Indirect proof, or proof through the impossible, was also well
known to Aristotle and adopted by the medievals.) Parsons shows that these three
basic principles together are sufficient for the derivation of the whole
classical syllogistic system, but in fact they allow us to go much further. Medieval
logicians extended the classical system of syllogistic in a variety of
interesting ways, so as to include quantification in predicate position, singular term
predicates, negative terms, anaphoric terms, genitives, demonstratives,
sentences with verbs other than the copula etc. Parsons shows that, on the
basis of the three primitive principles, and adding a minimum of inference
rules so as to cover the new cases in the expanded language, again one obtains
a coherent, elegant unique system. (The concern with systematicity also seems
to be one of the main driving forces of the project.) The goal is thus that of developing
a system that corresponds quite closely to what medieval authors recognized as
valid logical principles, at least within the scope of the phenomena that the
book addresses, on the basis of the three basic principles. (Parsons readily
recognizes that there is much more to medieval logical theories than what the
book covers – p. 5.) In the opinion of this reviewer, Parsons fully achieves
this goal.
The book also has a few peculiar features; for
example, the grey boxes entitled ‘Applications’ scattered along the different chapters,
containing what can be described as ‘exercises for the reader’ (the solutions are
however not to be found in the book). As a matter of fact, this reviewer happens to know that,
initially, Parsons conceived this book as something like a textbook on medieval
logic; but the project then changed in nature along the way. However, besides
the ‘Applications’ boxes, there are still other traces of the book’s previous
incarnation as a textbook, in particular chapters in which there are very few
references to secondary literature – a sensible choice for a textbook, but
perhaps less sensible for a book that intends to be ‘scholarly’ at least to
some extent. (Especially chapters 1 and 2, on Aristotelian syllogistic, do not
refer much to the vast and interesting secondary literature on the topic.)
Indeed, scholars closer to the historical end of the spectrum
alluded to above might object to the absence of extensive discussions on the
existing secondary literature, or else to the somewhat restricted collection of
texts examined (though Parsons does provide quite extensive textual
corroboration for the principles that he attributes to medieval logicians), or even
to the lack of a more general historical embedding of the discussions.
More generally, I suspect that a number of historically-minded medievalists will
not recognize Parsons’ project with this book as a legitimate one. In
particular, he does not pay much attention to what medieval logicians
themselves did with their logical systems; instead, he adopts a meta-level perspective to investigate properties of the systems as such. (What
medieval logicians were first and foremost interested in was arguably the application of logical theories and
principles, given that logic (broadly understood) provided the methodology for
investigations in all fields of inquiry.) But others, including logicians, linguists,
non-historian philosophers, and those scholars of medieval logic sympathetic to
the systematic end of the spectrum, will likely view Parsons’ project with this book as one very much worth pursuing, and will be impressed by the mastery with
which it is carried out.
In the limited confines of this review, I’ve chosen to focus
on explaining the nature of the project, in the hope that this will allow the
reader to determine whether she belongs to the target audience of the book or
not. In effect, this is a book likely to provoke extreme reactions. Some will dislike
it, and will worry in particular about the somewhat anachronistic picture of
medieval logic painted in the book. Others will love it for its skilled
application of modern logical and linguistic techniques to the medieval
material, presenting it with a systematicity not to be found elsewhere (neither
in the medieval authors themselves nor in the recent secondary literature). Some others might be of two minds, feeling the pull in both directions. But
without a doubt, the book is a milestone in medieval logic scholarship.
Catarina Dutilh Novaes
Faculty of Philosophy – University of Groningen
Having also been asked to review the book, for Philosophical Quarterly, I refrained from reading your review until after I'd written mine, but having sent that off last week, I was quite interested to see that yours and my feelings about it, not surprisingly, coincide to a large degree.
ReplyDelete