Problems with reductio proofs: assuming the impossible
By Catarina Dutilh Novaes
(Cross-posted at NewAPPS)
This is a series of posts with sections of the paper on reductio ad absurdum from a dialogical perspective that I am working on right now. This is Part II, here is Part I. In this post I discuss issues in connection with the first step in a reductio argument, that of assuming the impossible.
=====================
(Cross-posted at NewAPPS)
This is a series of posts with sections of the paper on reductio ad absurdum from a dialogical perspective that I am working on right now. This is Part II, here is Part I. In this post I discuss issues in connection with the first step in a reductio argument, that of assuming the impossible.
=====================
We
can think of a reductio ad absurdum as having three main components, following
Proclus’ description:
(i) Assuming
the initial hypothesis.
(ii)
Leading the hypothesis to absurdity.
(iii)
Concluding the contradictory of the initial hypothesis.
I discuss two problems pertaining to (i) in this post, and two
problems pertaining to (iii) in the next post. (ii) is not itself unproblematic,
and we have seen for example that Maria worries whether the ‘usual’ rules for
reasoning still apply once we’ve entered the impossible world established by
(i). Moreover, the problematic status of (i) arises to a great extent from its perceived
pragmatic conflict with (ii). But the focus will be on issues
arising in connection with (i) and (iii).
A
reductio proof starts with the assumption of precisely that which we want to
prove is impossible (or false). As we’ve seen, this seems to create a feeling
of cognitive dissonance in (some) reasoners: “I do not know what is true and
what I pretend [to be] true.” (Maria) This may seem surprising at first sight:
don’t we all regularly reason on the basis of false propositions, such as in
counterfactual reasoning? (“If I had eaten a proper meal earlier today, I
wouldn’t be so damn hungry now!”) However, as a matter of fact, there is
considerable empirical evidence suggesting that dissociating one’s beliefs from
reasoning is a very complex task, cognitively speaking (to ‘pretend that
something is true’, in Maria’s terms). The belief bias literature, for example,
has amply demonstrated the effect of belief on reasoning, even when
participants are told to focus only on the connections between premises and
conclusions. Moreover, empirical studies of reasoning behavior among adults
with low to no schooling show their reluctance to reason with premises of which
they have no knowledge (Harris 2000; Dutilh Novaes 2013). From this
perspective, reasoning on the basis of hypotheses or suppositions may well be
something that requires some sort of training (e.g. schooling) to be mastered.
For
our purposes, it may be useful to distinguish a number of different cases
involving reasoning with false or impossible hypotheses:
- The hypothesis may be false or impossible, without me in fact knowing that it is false or impossible (indeed, I may be in the process of investigating precisely that).
- The hypothesis may be false or impossible, and I know it to be false or impossible, but I want to see what would be the case if it were true (counterfactual reasoning).
- The hypothesis may be false or impossible, I know it to be false or impossible, and I am assuming it precisely with the goal of showing it to be false or impossible (a reductio argument).
In
the narrow sense adopted here, only the last case counts as true reductios ad
absurdum. My claim is that, while the first and even the second cases describe
cognitive activities that human beings regularly engage in, also outside
circles of specialists, the third case introduces a much stronger component of
pragmatic awkwardness: to assume something precisely with the goal of showing
it to be false. In Leron’s terms (cited in the previous post), this corresponds to the act of
postulating a false/impossible world only to proceed to ‘destroy’ it (show it
to be false/impossible). Maria describes it as telling herself a ‘lie’ and
having to believe it.
Perhaps
this pragmatic awkwardness arises only due to a reasoner’s failure to
appreciate the difference between a categorical assertion and an
assumption/hypothesis. Indeed, in the examples typically offered to illustrate
the purported pervasiveness of reductio arguments ‘in the wild’, one usually
encounters arguments formulated as a conditional or hypothetical sentence (“If he gets here in time for supper, he'll have to fly like Superman”). However, the conventions for the formulation of a reductio proof in mathematics
do not display this general structure perspicuously. Usually, such proofs start
with ‘Suppose that A’; now, while the ‘Suppose that…’ operator should function
in much the same way, judging from Maria’s and Fabio’s reports it seems that reasoners
feel they must truly commit to the truth of the initial hypothesis while
leading it towards absurdity. In effect, this is precisely what seems to be so
cognitively demanding: the conflicting roles of ‘pretending’ to believe the
hypothesis and of working towards its very destruction.
The
distinction between the initial assumption being merely false or else impossible
is also worth discussing in some detail. On most theories of (mental)
propositional attitudes, having an attitude towards a false proposition is for
the most part unproblematic: false propositions are much as true propositions
in terms of their semantics (spelled out in e.g. truth-conditional terms, or
use-based accounts, or what have you). Just as I can believe something that is
false, I should be able to suppose, i.e. entertain the possibility of,
something that is false (even if I know
it to be false, which is not compatible with belief).
But
matters become considerably more delicate once we are dealing with impossible propositions. While it is not
necessarily the case that every reductio argument will start by assuming an
impossibility, this is indeed what happens in many paradigmatic cases –
certainly if we accept that mathematical truths are necessary truths, and thus
mathematical falsities are necessary falsities, i.e. impossibilities. In the Tractatus, Wittgenstein (in)famously
claimed that impossibility cannot be expressed, as it cannot be depicted;
impossible thoughts cannot be conceived, and impossible propositions cannot be
meaningfully formulated. Even though most of us have surely outgrown the
Tractarian conception of propositions, we still seem to be stuck with the
problem of providing a satisfactory philosophical account of impossible
thoughts. As well put by Jago:
Impossible thoughts might appear nothing more than a quirky feature of the way we can meaningfully represent the world around us. It may come as something of a surprise, therefore, to learn that just about every major philosophical theory of content and meaning is unable to account for impossible thoughts. Moreover, a wide variety of philosophical views converge in a kind of pressure group against the existence of impossible thoughts. (Jago 2014, 3)
Jago
then goes on to detail how and why different philosophical frameworks fail
miserably to account for impossible thoughts and impossible content. What is
particularly unsatisfying is that these frameworks (including the Tractarian
framework) tend to treat all impossible thoughts/propositions as having the
same content: in possible world semantics, for example, all impossible
propositions have the same meaning, namely they correspond to the empty set
(the domain being the collection of all possible worlds). But the initial
assumptions of reductio proofs in mathematics surely do not all have the same
content! If they did, each such reductio proof would be essentially identical
to all others, and this is obviously an undesirable result.
In
other words, a philosophical account of reductio ad absurdum requires a sufficiently
fine-grained account of impossible thoughts/propositions if we are to make
sense of the initial step, that of putting forward the initial hypothesis.
Naturally, there are many other reasons to look for adequate theories of the
impossible, and some proposals have been put forward (e.g. (Jago 2014)). Here,
I will not venture into offering yet another theory of impossible thoughts; for
my purposes, it is enough to note that this is yet another point where reductio
ad absurdum is not a straightforward affair from a philosophical perspective.
In
sum, there are two problems with the initial speech act in a reductio: the
general problem of representing impossible content so as to make sense of the
speech act of assuming an impossibility; and the pragmatic and equally serious
problem of the awkwardness of putting forward a proposition (even if as an
assumption or hypothesis), ‘pretending’ to believe it, precisely in order to
show it to be false/impossible. It is this second problem which will receive a natural
solution once one adopts a dialogical perspective.
(To be continued...)
(To be continued...)
One natural idea for making reductio proofs more palatable to those who find this first stage problematic, which you suggest by mentioning counterfactuals, is to use appropriate "subjunctive" language. For example, instead of saying, "Suppose that the square root of 2 is rational," one would say, "Suppose that the square root of 2 were rational." Then one is not telling a lie any more: one is merely considering the consequences of a hypothesis.
ReplyDeleteYes, this seems right. As I suggested, one of the problems with classical presentations of reductio proofs is that they adopt categorical language to talk about the hypothesis to be refuted.
DeleteYou distinguish between three cases which may occur whenever someone deals with a reductio. It occurred to me that the following may occur: One person claims A to be the case, but his friend insists on ¬A. Genuinely interested in discovering the truth together, they then investigate and by means of a reductio, assert A after assuming ¬A. This is in line with Case 2.
ReplyDeleteHere on out, should either party, pedagogically speaking, wish to educate anyone else on the matter, wouldn't they fall under Case 3, when they wish to share unless they specifically had it in mind to act out their former ignorance?
In other words, it struck me that Case 3 may just be a retelling of activities that fell under case 2 where, and as you point out this is important, the one doing the retelling has conviction regarding the outcome. Depending on what one thinks, it may be the case that *every* event that falls under Case 3 is a retelling of case 2 from a new standpoint of knowledge e.g. a teacher or textbook who has resolved the "final gap problem," or a description of such an event.
tunceli
ReplyDeletebingöl
gümüşhane
edirne
kastamonu
462