The beauty (?) of mathematical proofs -- explanatory proofs
By Catarina Dutilh Novaes
This is the fourth installment of my series of posts on the beauty, function, and explanation in mathematical proofs (Part I is here; Part II is here; Part III is here). In this post I present a brief survey of the debates in the literature on what it means for a mathematical proof to be explanatory.
=============
Quite a bit has been said on explanation
and mathematical proofs in recent decades (Mancosu & Pincock 2012).
Although the topic itself has an old and distinguished pedigree (it was
extensively discussed by ancient authors such as Aristotle and Proclus, as well
as by Renaissance and early modern authors – Mancosu 2011, section 5), in
recent decades the debate was (re-)ignited by the work of Steiner in the late
19070s, thus generating a wealth of discussions. This brief overview could not
possibly do justice to the richness of this material, so what follows is a
selection of themes particularly pertinent for the present purposes.
The issue of what makes scientific
theories or arguments more generally explanatory is again a question as old as
philosophy itself; indeed, it is of the main issues discussed in Aristotle’s
theory of science (in particular in the Posterior
Analytics). The traditional, Aristotelian account has it that a scientific
explanation is truly explanatory iff it accurately tracks the causal relations
underlying the phenomena that it seeks to explain. To mention a worn-out but
still useful example: the fact that it is 25 degrees C outside and the fact
that a well-functioning thermometer indicates ’25 C’ (typically) occur
simultaneously, but an explanation of the former phenomenon in terms of the
latter gets the causal order the wrong way round: it is the outside temperature
of 25 degrees C that causes
thermometers to indicate ’25 C’, not the converse.
In the 20th century, the issue regained
prominence, at first with Hempel’s (1965) formulation of his famous Deductive-Nomological
model of scientific explanation. In the spirit of the logical positivistic
rejection of all things metaphysical, Hempel’s goal was to offer an account of
scientific explanation that would do away with traditional but dubious (i.e.
metaphysical) concepts such as causation. Much criticism has been voiced
against Hempel’s model on different grounds, and one line of attack, espoused
in particular by Salmon (1984), emphasized the unsuitability of doing away with
causation altogether.
When it comes to mathematics, the question them becomes: are
mathematical proofs explanatory in the same way as scientific theories are? It
is in no way obvious that a causal
story can be told for mathematical proofs. Does it make sense to say that some
mathematical truths can cause some
other mathematical truths? For this to be the case, one would presumably have
to accept not only the independent existence of mathematical entities, but also
the idea that they can causally influence each other. Now, while this is not as
such an incoherent position (and seems to be something that a full-blown
Platonist such as Hardy might be happy to endorse), it comes with heavy
metaphysical as well as epistemological (as per Benacerraff’s challenge) costs.
And thus, most authors involved in these debates seem to
recognize that a full-blown causal story is unlikely to do a good job in the
case of mathematical proofs. They then endeavor to look for different accounts
of the explanatoriness of mathematical proofs, which may eventually still be
reconcilable with broader conceptions of scientific explanation, or, if not,
would lead to mathematical exceptionalism – i.e. the idea that explanation in
mathematics is a different beast altogether. (For the present purposes, this
specific issue will be set aside.)
In his seminal work in the late 1970s, Steiner introduced the
notion of a characterizing property
as what distinguishes explanatory from non-explanatory proofs: “an explanatory
proof makes reference to a characterizing property of an entity or structure
mentioned in the theorem, such that from the proof it is evident that the
result depends on the property” (Steiner 1978, 143). The notion of dependence
clearly seeks to capture a non-causal analogue of the notion of causation in
scientific explanation more generally. As described by Mancosu & Pincock
(2012, 16), “Steiner argues that these dependence relations require both that
the entity or structure be uniquely picked out by some characterizing property,
and that the explanatory proof be part of a family of proofs where this
property is varied.”
Notice that the idea of a ‘family of proofs’ seems related to
Hardy’s generality requirement that the core idea of a proof be present in
other relevant proofs (see here for Hardy's criteria). In turn, the idea that an explanatory proof makes it
evident that the result depends on the characterizing property resembles
Hardy’s notion of inevitability, and arguably brings along economy/simplicity
as well.
Steiner’s account has been criticized for a number of reasons,
but it is fair to say that much of the debate in recent decades is still tied
to how he framed the issue. As pointed out by Mancosu (2011), Steiner’s is a
local account, i.e. explanatoriness is a local property of a given proof. In
contrast, Philip Kitcher’s (1989) approach may be described as global/holistic in that
the explanatoriness of proofs is viewed in the broader context of
(mathematical) knowledge as a whole. For Kitcher, the key notion is that of unification: “an explanatory proof in
pure mathematics is one that is part of a small collection of argument patterns
that allows the derivation of the mathematical claims that we accept.” (Mancosu
& Pincock 2012, 15) We are now reminded of Hardy’s global properties
of seriousness and depth.
A presupposition running through the philosophical literature
is that there really is a meaningful distinction between proofs that are explanatory
and proofs that are not. ((Resnik &
Kushner 1987) is one of the few exceptions.) The distinction is often
formulated in terms of a distinction between proofs that merely establish that the conclusion is the case (that
is, if the premises are the case) and proofs establishing why the conclusion is the case; the former merely demonstrate,
while the latter explain (Colyvan
2102, 76).[1]
(Recall that, as famously claimed by van Fraassen (1980), explanations are
answers o ‘why’ questions.) The point is obviously that explanatoriness is (presumably)
a desirable property in a proof, and all things being equal, mathematicians (should)
prefer explanatory proofs over non-explanatory ones. However, a number of
questions immediately arise: is this distinction absolute, or is it
context-dependent? Is it a sharp distinction, or is it one allowing for degrees
such that explanatoriness becomes a comparative notion? (A proof is not
explanatory an sich, but more
explanatory than other proofs, as well as potentially less explanatory than
others.)
Not coincidentally, the same questions can be raised
concerning the purported beauty of proofs. Is a beautiful proof beautiful in an
absolute sense, i.e. is beauty an objective, absolute property of certain proofs?
Or can a proof be viewed as beautiful by one person but as not particularly
beautiful by another person, while both judgments are legitimate and ‘correct’
in some sense or another? Is beauty best viewed as a sharp category, or should
it be viewed as a comparative notion? In both cases, what is being tracked is
the phenomenon of mathematicians displaying predilections
for certain (kinds of) proofs over others, which suggests that more is at stake
than simply establishing the truth of a theorem. Perhaps the proofs that
mathematicians tend to prefer are more beautiful than others, or else they are
more explanatory than others, and if this is so, we may wonder what it is that
these preferred proofs have in common.
FULL SERIES:
References
Colyvan, M.,2012, Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics. Cambridge: CUP.
Hempel, C., 1965, Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, New York: Free Press.
Kitcher, P., 1989, ‘Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World’, in Scientific Explanation, P. Kitcher and W. Salmon, 410–505. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Mancosu, P., 2011, 'Explanation in mathematics'. In E. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Mancosu, P. & Pincock, C., 2012, 'Mathematical explanation'. Oxford Bibliographies.
Resnik, M., and D. Kushner, 1987, “Explanation, Independence, and Realism in Mathematics”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38: 141–158.
Salmon, W., 1984, Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Steiner, M., 1978, “Mathematical Explanation”, Philosophical Studies, 34: 135–151.
Van Fraassen, B., 1980, The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press
[1] Recall Rota’s description of a
beautiful proof as “when it leads us to perceive the actual, not the logical
inevitability of the statement that is being proved”.
ReplyDeleteThe one-to-one interaction between the manager and the student is a perfect way tobest assignment services obtain rich benefits from the most from the article modifying solutions.
Your mathematical proof and solving detail absolutely work it thanks for share it paraphrasing a poem .
ReplyDelete