An almost-Dutch Book argument for the Principal Principle
People often talk about the synchronic Dutch Book argument for Probabilism and the diachronic Dutch Strategy argument for Conditionalization. But the synchronic Dutch Book argument for the Principal Principle is mentioned less. That's perhaps because, in one sense, there couldn't possibly be such an argument. As the Converse Dutch Book Theorem shows, providing you satisfy Probabilism, there can be no Dutch Book made against you -- that is, there is no sets of bets, each of which you will consider fair or favourable on its own, but which, when taken together, lead to a sure loss for you. So you can violate the Principal Principle without being vulnerable to a sure loss, providing your satisfy Probabilism. However, there is a related argument for the Principal Principle. And conversations with a couple of philosophers recently made me think it might be worth laying it out.
Here is the result on which the argument is based:
(I) Suppose your credences violate the Principal Principle but satisfy Probabilism. Then there is a book of bets and a price such that: (i) you consider that price favourable for that book -- that is, your subjective expectation of the total net gain is positive; (ii) every possible objective chance function considers that price unfavourable -- that is, the objective expectation of the total net gain is guaranteed to be negative.
(II) Suppose your credences satisfy both the Principal Principle and Probabilism. Then there is no book of bets and a price such that: (i) you consider that price favourable for that book; (ii) every possible objective chance function considers that price unfavourable.
Put another way:
(I') Suppose your credences violate the Principal Principle. There are two actions and such that: you prefer to , but every possible objective chance function prefers to .
(II') Suppose your credences satisfy the Principal Principle. For any two actions and : if every possible objective chance function prefers to , then you prefer to .
To move from (I) and (II) to (I') and (II'), let be the action of accepting the bets in and let be the action of rejecting them.
The proof splits into two parts:
(1) First, we note that a credence function satisfies the Principal Principle iff is in the closed convex hull of the set of possible chance functions.
(2) Second, we prove that:
(2I) If a probability function lies outside the closed convex hull of a set of probability functions , then there is a book of bets and a price such the expected total net gain from that book at that price by the lights of is positive, while the expected total net gain from that book at that price by the lights of each in is negative.
(2II) If a probability function lies inside the closed convex hull of a set of probability functions , then there is no book of bets and a price such the expected total net gain from that book
at that price by the lights of is positive, while the expected
total net gain from that book at that price by the lights of each in
is negative.
Here's the proof of (2), which I lift from my recent justification of linear pooling -- the same technique is applicable since the Principal Principle essentially says that you should set your credences by applying linear pooling to the possible objective chances.
First:
Lemma 1
If is a probability function on , the expected payoff of the book of bets by the lights of is
Lemma 2
Suppose is a probability function on , is a set of probability functions on , and is the closed convex hull of . Then, if , then there is a vector and such that, for all in ,
Proof of Lemma 2. Suppose . Then let be the closest point in to . Then let . Then, for any in , the angle between and is obtuse and thus . So, since and , we have . And hence . What's more, since is closed, is not a limit point of , and thus there is such that for all in . Thus, there is such that , for all in .
We now derive (2I) and (2II) from Lemmas 1 and 2:
Let be the set of possible objective chance functions. If violates the Principal Principle, then is not in . Thus, by Lemma 2, there is a book of bets and such that, for any objective chance function in , . By Lemma 1, is the expected payout of the book of bets by the lights of , while is the expected payout of the book of bets by the lights of . Now, suppose we were to offer an agent with credence function the book of bets for the price of . Then this would have positive expected payoff by the lights of , but negative expected payoff by the lights of each in . This gives (2I).
(2II) then holds because, when is in the closed convex hull of , its expectation of a random variable is in the closed convex hull of the expectations of that random variable by the lights of the probability functions in . Thus, if the expectation of a random variable is negative by the lights of all the probability functions in , then its expectation by the lights of is not positive.
Here is the result on which the argument is based:
(I) Suppose your credences violate the Principal Principle but satisfy Probabilism. Then there is a book of bets and a price such that: (i) you consider that price favourable for that book -- that is, your subjective expectation of the total net gain is positive; (ii) every possible objective chance function considers that price unfavourable -- that is, the objective expectation of the total net gain is guaranteed to be negative.
(II) Suppose your credences satisfy both the Principal Principle and Probabilism. Then there is no book of bets and a price such that: (i) you consider that price favourable for that book; (ii) every possible objective chance function considers that price unfavourable.
Put another way:
(I') Suppose your credences violate the Principal Principle. There are two actions
(II') Suppose your credences satisfy the Principal Principle. For any two actions
To move from (I) and (II) to (I') and (II'), let
The proof splits into two parts:
(1) First, we note that a credence function
(2) Second, we prove that:
(2I) If a probability function
(2II) If a probability function
Here's the proof of (2), which I lift from my recent justification of linear pooling -- the same technique is applicable since the Principal Principle essentially says that you should set your credences by applying linear pooling to the possible objective chances.
First:
- Let
be the set of possible worlds - Let
be the set of propositions over which our probability functions are defined. So each is a subset of .
- We represent a probability function
defined on as a vector in , namely, . - Given a proposition
in and a stake in , we define the bet as follows: So pays out if is true and if is false. - We represent the book of bets
as a vector in , namely, .
Lemma 1
If
Lemma 2
Suppose
Proof of Lemma 2. Suppose
We now derive (2I) and (2II) from Lemmas 1 and 2:
Let
(2II) then holds because, when
It's worth taking a longer look at this article. Dentist near me
ReplyDeleteDe beste online casino’s onderscheiden zich in bonussen en uitbetalingen. De odds in een topcasino zijn gewoon beter dan in een casino dat wat kleiner is of een wat beperkter assortiment heeft. In topcasino’s zijn de winstkansen niet per se groter, maar je kunt op meer verschillende manieren inzetten.
ReplyDeletehttps://onlinecasinotop100.nl/