I've just signed a contract with Cambridge University Press to write
a book on the Dutch Book Argument
for their Elements in Decision Theory and Philosophy series. So over
the next few months, I'm going to be posting some bits and pieces as I
get properly immersed in the literature.
-----
Many Bayesians formulate the update norm of Bayesian epistemology as follows:
Bayesian Conditionalization If
(i) your credence function at is ,
(ii) your credence function at a later time is ,
(iii) is the strongest evidence you acquire between and ,
(iv) is in ,
then rationality requires that, if , then for all in ,
I don't. One reason you might fail to conditionalize between and is that you re-evaluate the options between those times. You might disavow the prior that you had at the earlier time, perhaps decide it was too biased in one way or another, or not biased enough; perhaps you come to think that it doesn't give enough consideration to the explanatory power one hypothesis would have were it true, or gives too much consideration to the adhocness of another hypothesis; and so on. Now, it isn't irrational to change your mind. So surely it can't be irrational to fail to conditionalize as a result of changing your mind in this way. On this, I agree with van Fraassen.
Instead, I prefer to formulate the update norm as follows -- I borrow the name from Kenny Easwaran:
Plan Conditionalization If
(i) your credence function at is ,
(ii) between and you will receive evidence from the partition ,
(iii) each is in
(iv) at , your updating plan is , so that is the credence function you will adopt if ,
then rationality requires that, if , then for all in ,
I want to do two things in this post. First, I'll offer what I think is a new proof of the Dutch Strategy or Diachronic Dutch Book Theorem that justifies Plan Conditionalization (I haven't come across it elsewhere, though Ray Briggs and I used the trick at the heart of it for our accuracy dominance theorem in
this paper). Second, I'll explore how that might help us justify other norms of updating that concern situations in which you don't come to learn any proposition with certainty. We will see that we can use the proof I give to justify the following standard constraint on updating rules: Suppose the evidence I receive between and is not captured by any of the propositions to which I assign a credence -- that is, there is no proposition to which I assign a credence that is true at all and only the worlds at which I receive the evidence I actually receive between and . As a result, there is no proposition that I learn with certainty as a result of receiving that evidence. Nonetheless, I should update my credence function from to in such a way that it is possible to extend my earlier credence function to a credence function so that: (i) does assign a credence to , and (ii) my later credence in a proposition is the credence that this extended credence function assigns to conditional on me receiving evidence -- that is, . That is, I should update
as if I had assigned a credence to at the earlier time and then updated by conditionalizing on it.
Here's the Dutch Strategy or Diachronic Dutch Book Theorem for Plan Conditionalization:
Definition (Conditionalizing pair) Suppose is a credence function and is an updating rule defined on . We say that
is a conditionalizing pair if, whenever , then for all , .
Dutch Strategy Theorem Suppose is not a conditionalizing pair. Then
(i) there are two acts and such that prefers to , and
(ii) for each , there are two acts and such that prefers to ,
and, for each , has greater utility than at all worlds at which is true.
We'll now give the proof of this.
First, we describe a way of representing pairs . Both and each are defined on the same set . So we can represent by the vector in , and we can represent each by the vector in . And we can represent by concatenating all of these representations to give:
which is a vector in .
Second, we use this representation to give an alternative characterization of conditionalizing pairs. First, three pieces of notation:
- Let be the set of all possible worlds.
- For any in , abuse notation and write also for the credence function on such that if is true at , and if is false at .
- For any in , let where is the element of the partition that is true at .
Lemma 1 If is not a conditionalizing pair, then is not in the convex hull of , which we write .
Proof of Lemma 1. If is in , then there are such that
(1) ,
(2)
(3) .
By (2), we have . So by (3), we have So, if , then .
Third, we use this alternative characterization of conditionalizing pairs to specify the acts in question. Suppose is not a conditionalizing pair. Then is outside . Now, let be the orthogonal projection of into . Then let . That is, and . Now pick in . Then the angle between and is obtuse and thus
Thus, define the acts , , and as follows:
- The utility of at is :
- The utility of at is 0;
- The utility of at is ;
- The utility of at is 0.
Then the expected utility of by the lights of is , while the expected utility of is 0, so prefers to . And the expected utility of by the lights of is , while the expected utility of is 0, so prefers to . But the utility of at is
where is true at . While the utility of at is 0.
This completes our proof.
You might be forgiven for wondering why we are bothering to give an alternative proof for a theorem that is already well-known. David Lewis proved the Dutch Strategy Theorem in a handout for a seminar at Princeton in 1972, Paul Teller then reproduced it (with full permission and acknowledgment) in a paper in 1973, and Lewis finally published his handout in 1997 in his collected works. Why offer a new proof?
It turns out that this style of proof is actually a little more powerful. To see why, it's worth comparing it to an alternative proof of the Dutch Book Theorem for Probabilism, which I described in
this post (it's not original to me, though I'm afraid I can't remember where I first saw it!). In the standard Dutch Book Theorem for Probabilism, we work through each of the axioms of the probability calculus, and say how you would Dutch Book an agent who violates it. The axioms are: Normalization, which says that and ; and Additivity, which says that . But consider an agent with credences only in the propositions , , and . Her credences are: , , . Then there is no axiom of the probability calculus that she violates. And thus the standard proof of the Dutch Book Theorem is no help in identifying any Dutch Book against her. Yet she is Dutch Bookable. And she violates a more expansive formulation of Probabilism that says, not only are you irrational if your credence function is not a probability function, but also if your credence function
cannot be extended to a probability function. So the standard proof of the Dutch Book Theorem can't establish this more expansive version. But the alternative proof I mentioned above can.
Now, something similar is true of the alternative proof of the Dutch Strategy Theorem that I offered above (I happened upon this while discussing Superconditionalizing with Jason Konek, who uses similar techniques in his argument for J-Kon, the alternative to Jeffrey's Probability Kinematics that he proposes in his paper,
'The Art of Learning', which was runner-up for last year's Sander's Prize in Epistemology). In Lewis' proof of that theorem: First, if you violate Plan Conditionalization, there must be and such that and . Then you place bets on , at the earlier time , and a bet on at . These bets then together lose you money in any world at which is true. Now, it might seem that you must have the required credences to make those bets just in virtue of violating Plan Conditionalization. But imagine the following is true of you: between and , you'll obtain evidence from the partition . And, at , you'll update on this evidence using the rule . That is, if , then you'll adopt the new credence function at time . Now, you don't assign credences to the propositions in . Perhaps this is because you don't have the conceptual resources to formulate these propositions. So while you will update using the rule , this is not a rule you consciously or explicitly adopt, since to state it would require you to use the propositions in . So it's more like you have a disposition to update in this way. Now, how might we state Plan Conditionalization for such an agent? We can't demand that , since is not defined. Rather, we demand that there is some extension of to a set of propositions that does include each such that . Thus, we have:
Plan Superconditionalization If
(i) your credence function at is ,
(ii) between and you will receive evidence from the partition ,
(iii) at , your updating plan is , so that is the credence function you plan to adopt if ,
then rationality requires that there is some extension of for which, if , then for all ,
And it turns out that we can adapt the proof above for this purpose. Say that is a superconditionalizing pair if there is an extension of such that, if , then for all , . Then we can prove that if is not a superconditionalizing pair, then is not in . Here's the proof from above adapted to our case: If is in , then there are such that
(1) ,
(2)
(3) .
Define the following extension of : . Then, by (3), we have So, if , then , as required.
Now, this is a reasonably powerful version of conditionalization. For instance, as Skyrms showed
here, if we make one or two further assumptions on the extension of to , we can derive Richard Jeffrey's Probability Kinematics from Plan Superconditionalization. That is, if the evidence will lead you to set your new credences across the partition to , respectively, so that , then your new credence must be , as Probability Kinematics demands. Thus, Plan Superconditionalization places a powerful constraint on updating rules for situations in which the proposition stating your evidence is not one to which you assign a credence. Other cases of this sort include the Judy Benjamin problem and the many cases in which MaxEnt is applied.
Dutch Strategy Theorem: Should "Suppose (c,c′) is not a conditionalizing pair" be "Suppose (c,c′) is a conditionalizing pair"?
ReplyDeleteHi Greg, I think it should be 'Suppose (c, c') is not a conditionalizing pair'. The idea is that, when (c, c') isn't a conditionalizing pair, we can create a Dutch Strategy against it. Here, I'm understanding a Dutch Strategy to be a choice between A and B at the earlier time and then a choice between A'i and B'i at the later time if the agent has learned Ei. I've not said anything about converse Dutch Books here, but I think they should hold for the usual reasons. Does that make sense?
DeleteI see. My worry is about scope: a banana and coconut are not a conditionalizing pair. For book arguments, you have the harness of elicitation to restrict you to the right sort of qualitative judgments for which a numerical representation can be assessed. I don't see an analogous constraint here.
DeleteThanks for sharing such an Amazing information, I Couldn't leave without reading your blog. I have read another good blog, I think you have read it too. click here Trend Micro belgie contacteren
ReplyDelete